Tuesday, July 23, 2013
Congratulations to Robbie George! ...
... on his richly deserved appointment as chair of the U.S. Commission on International Religious Freedom. From the news release:
Dr. Katrina Lantos Swett, USCIRF’s outgoing Chair and an appointee of Senate Majority Leader Harry Reid, announced Professor George’s selection. “I have been honored to work alongside Professor George this past year in the struggle to guarantee religious freedom abroad for people of every faith and shade of belief. He is a true human rights champion whose compassion for victims of oppression and wisdom about international religious freedom shine through all we have accomplished this past year. Our bipartisan Commission is united in its admiration for Professor George’s skills as an advocate and leader of the international religious freedom movement. The Commission is eager to continue its work under his able leadership.”
July 23, 2013 in Berg, Thomas | Permalink | Comments (0)
Some Draft Papers from "Intellectual Property and Religious Thought" Symposium
Readers may remember my posting about the great symposium on "Intellectual Property and Religious Thought" at St. Thomas in April. Papers from it, which are forthcoming in the University of St. Thomas Law Journal, are beginning to appear in draft form on SSRN. The symposium took up a wide range of issues, from the basic question how far ideas can be owned or "sequestered" (Paul Griffiths argued that in the classic early-modern Catholic intellectual tradition they cannot), to issues concerning new technology and social justice (human gene patents, patented seeds and their effect on farmers), to the role of social relationships and communities in innovation and creativity.
Perhaps unsurprisingly, a recurrent theme was that intellectual property, like many other areas of law, has become so obssessed with rights, and with the supposedly magical qualities of market transactions, that it has neglected the common good and the duties/responsibilities that society may properly demand of property holders. A couple papers in this vein have been posted on SSRN:
Alina Ng (MIssissippi College), "Finding Copyright's Core Content"; here's an excerpt from the abstract:
Framing the analysis of copyright laws within consequentialist frameworks as intellectual property scholars have conventionally tended to do, while important in studying the consequences of laws from a socio-economic perspective, has not yielded satisfactory answers to a more fundamental question about the proper content and scope of copyright laws. For many communities and societies with increasing humanistic interests and goals, this question about the law’s proper content is a perennial one. To answer this question, this paper draws from two sources. First, legal theories on natural law, which require as a general rule that man-made laws satisfy an objective moral standard, support a proposition that copyright laws have essential moral content that may be identified through reason. Second, catholic social teachings on the common good, respect for the life and dignity of the human person, and correlation of rights and responsibility offer a framework to inform and shape appropriate copyright laws and policies. This paper proposes that for the progress of science to be sustained, the core content of copyright laws must protect the conditions that contribute towards authentic forms of authorship and support the flourishing and thriving of relationship-oriented communities.
Shubha Ghosh (U Wisconsin), "Duties, Consequences, and Intellectual Property":
Drawing on Amartya Sen's discussion of The Bhagavad Gita and Hindu concepts of justice (niti and nyaya), this paper examines ethical issues related to the construction of intellectual property policy. The author analyzes deontic, or duty based, and consequentialist theories of law within the context of the debate between Arjuna and Krishna in The Gita. With respect to intellectual property, the author proposes a consequentialist theory of intellectual property based on the duties owed by an owner to other persons. This ethical theory is illustrated through the legal treatment of patents on medical diagnostics (Prometheus v Mayo) as well as on through the doctrines of fair use and first sale.
FInally, Bobbi Kwall (DePaul) has posted a written version of her fantastic lunch talk, "Remember the Sabbath Day and Enhance Your Creativity":
Beginning in the twentieth century, researchers examining creativity theory have begun to focus on the relationship between a break period known as incubation and enhanced creativity. This relationship centers around the benefits of unconscious processing. Thus, science now seems to be documenting the benefits of the Jewish Sabbath, an institution dating back over three thousand years, during which time all work-day activities are suspended. This Article outlines the theological predicate of the Jewish Sabbath and surveys the history and development of the Sabbath laws. It then discusses the recent research in the social sciences and provides a theoretical bridge from this research to the significance of the Sabbath for enhancing human creativity.
There's more good stuff to come when the symposium issue appears.
July 23, 2013 in Berg, Thomas | Permalink | Comments (0)
Some Thoughts on Political Psychology and a Couple of Questions for Tom
Reading Tom's thoughtful comment below is a pleasure. He takes each of Michael's and Rick's respective pieces, notes and elaborates on areas of agreement, and proceeds to explain with care where he may have a different view. I should also say that I very much respect and admire the work that he, Professor Laycock, Professor Wilson, Rick, and Michael (among others) have been doing on the issue of religious exemptions and same-sex marriage.
The tail end of Tom's post caught my eye: "In fact, in the long run, I think, the best hope for arguing for religious liberty is not to refuse sympathy for gay couples' efforts to live out their deep, pervasive commitments--but rather to accord them sympathy and claim similar sympathy for the deep, pervasive commitments of religious believers individually and in their institutions. It is frequently argued that activists for SSM, "aggressive and uncompromising," will never return that sympathy. But the struggle here is, as in so many other cases, to convince those in the middle. My own judgment is that as time goes on, the effort to refuse same-sex marriage will increasingly alienate those in the middle, forfeiting the chance to win them to a "live and let live" approach that will protect traditional religious organizations' ability to maintain their identities."
Here are a few friendly questions for Tom about this paragraph, offered up in an appreciative spirit. The overarching question is: Why is this your judgment? More specifically, what is the basis for the judgment that, as a predictive matter, a metaphorical cessation of hostilities on the substantive question of same-sex marriage will, as time goes on, result in a metaphorical cessation of hostilities on the substantive question of religious exemption? It seems to me that in order to reach that conclusion, one would have to believe certain other things, too--things which are not necessarily particular to this debate but may reflect more general beliefs about political psychology. It is those more general beliefs that I want to explore and think about in this post.
First, it seems to me that one would need to believe in a theory of what I'll call sympathetic reciprocity in politics (the word "sympathy" appears several times in Tom's comment), which might go something like this: in the realm of politics or policy-making, over the long-term, people remember and respect concessions, and they respond to those concessions with concessions of their own. They reward sympathy with sympathy. And eventually, with time and good faith, a people that holds radically different beliefs about the good life can achieve a modus vivendi--a 'live and let live' ethic--by observing a policy of sympathetic reciprocity.
Setting aside this particular controversy, though, I wonder whether that is an accurate description of the reasons that political concessions generally get made. We do not accept a 'live and let live' ethic for many issues of public concern; we do accept them for others; and the issues for which we do and do not accept such an ethic are relatively stable but always changing. But is the extent to which we accept such an ethic in turn dependent on a theory of sympathetic reciprocity--that is, on the extent to which those with whom we disagree have previously extended sympathy toward the policy that we champion and that they disavow? Does politics have a sympathetic memory in this way, and does it reward those who moderate their views with reciprocal concessions? Or is the acceptance of a 'live and let live' ethic more dependent on considerations of public salience, political prestige and influence, effective rhetoric, cost, the vagaries of public opinion, cultural trends--in sum, is it far more dependent on considerations of cultural and political power? I grant that this is a gloomier view than I think is at work in Tom's comment. I'm not sure that I endorse it in an unqualified way. But I hope Tom might say a little bit more about why--on what grounds--he holds (or seems to hold) to the comparatively sunny view of sympathetic reciprocity in politics.
Second, I wonder about the more specific question of the political psychology of what Tom has called 'the middle.' In theory, a legal right ought never to be compromised by political considerations, but in practice, rights are traded off all the time. Yet we would need an extremely acute sense of the middle's opinion of the strength and importance of the rights in conflict in order to predict with confidence whether the middle will believe that trade-offs of rights are warranted, and that a policy of 'live and let live' is justified. A policy of 'live and let live' was viable for, e.g., the Amish in Wisconsin v. Yoder in part because the common feeling (as perceived and articulated by the Court) was that an accommodation in that context could be bought cheaply. The Amish are a small minority that is largely invisible to the middle, and so the price of a 'live and let live' policy was low enough for the middle to display its magnanimous quality. In today's climate, when considerations of equality and nondiscrimination are at stake, I wonder whether the calculus is different: the middle may well believe that the right of exemption is purchased at a much dearer cost.
In fact, I do not have a reliable sense for just how strong a commitment the middle has to the legal right to same-sex marriage. Tolerance is not embrace. I also do not have a reliable sense for how powerfully committed the middle is to religious liberty. On the one hand, there are signs that Americans are increasingly disenchanted with religious freedom, that they believe the First Amendment protects too much, and that of the rights that it does protect, religious freedom is comparatively unimportant. On the other hand, that's only one survey, and, as I say, the degree of commitment of the middle to the legal right to same-sex marriage is also difficult to measure precisely.
The middle is in the middle for a reason: their support or opposition is middling. But there are different degrees of political support, and those gradations will be relevant to predictions about what the middle is likely to do when rights clash. The question I have for Tom on this front is: isn't the viability of the ‘live and let live’ strategy dependent on having a reliably accurate measure of the middle's views? Without that, one may be misled by an attractively upbeat, but perhaps overly sanguine (and how would we know?), political psychology that does not reflect the middle's sense of the world.
July 23, 2013 in DeGirolami, Marc | Permalink | Comments (5)
The French and American revolutions, "positive" and "assertive" secularism
I'm a bit late posting this -- I had meant to earlier in the month, in the context of the Fortnight for Freedom -- but I think it's still worth reading. Thomas Howard discusses, in "July 4, July 14, and the Religious Question" the important distinction between (a) the American Revolution and the "positive secularism" it produced and (b) the French Revolution and the "aggressive secularism" it brought about.
The discussion echoes, of course, our Pope Emeritus's frequent discussions of (and praise for) "healthy secularity" (which I discuss here and elsewhere).
July 23, 2013 in Garnett, Rick | Permalink | Comments (0)
Mary Ann Glendon and "The Structure of Religious Freedom"
Here, at Public Discourse, is a shorter version of a paper I shared at a recent conference, sponsored by the Notre Dame Program on Church, State, and Society, dedicated to exploring and celebrating the work of Prof. Mary Ann Glendon. Here is a bit:
[C]onstitutionalism depends for its success on the existence and activities of non-state authorities. It should protect, but it also requires, self-governing religious communities that operate and evolve outside and independent of governments. It is a mistake to regard “religion” merely as a private practice, or even as a social phenomenon, to which constitutions respond or react. Instead, the ongoing enterprise of constitutionalism is one to which religious freedom contributes. Human rights depend for protection and flourishing not only on enforceable constraints on government but also on the structure of the social order. With respect to matters of polity, doctrine, leadership, and membership, the autonomy that religious institutions enjoy simultaneously contributes to and benefits from that structure.
July 23, 2013 in Garnett, Rick | Permalink | Comments (21)
Monday, July 22, 2013
Hobby Lobby (and the Becket Fund) secure a preliminary injunction of the mandate
This happened a few days ago, but is still worth noting. Congratulations to the Becket Fund lawyers on this important victory.
July 22, 2013 in Garnett, Rick | Permalink | Comments (0)
Friday, July 19, 2013
Brief Response to Tom Berg
Thanks very much, Tom, for engaging my brief commentary in Commonweal on United States v. Windsor.
1. I explicate the right--the human right--to religious and moral freedom, and explain why we are warranted in concluding that the right is entrenched in the constitutional law of the United States, both in my new book and, more recently, in an article that will soon be published in the Journal of Law and Religion. The article is available here.
2. You ask: "Michael, given your argument, do you think that Roe and Casey were rightly decided--and rightly decided simply because restrictions on abortion are 'widely contested' (without some need to establish that they seriously impose on women's physical autonomy or life plans)?" The way you formulate your question reflects, I think, a misunderstanding of the content of the right to religious and moral freedom. About the right, please see my first response, above.
About the constitutional controversy over the criminalization of abortion: In the final chapter of my new book, I bring both the right to moral equality (which I explicate in the book) and the right to religious and moral freedom to bear on the Abortion Cases--and conclude both that Roe v. Wade was rightly decided (which is not to say, rightly reasoned), principally because of the right to moral equality, and that Doe v. Bolton was wrongly decided. In reaching that twofold conclusion, I am aligned with what I understand to be the position my former teacher Ruth Ginsburg expressed when she was a member of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit.
3. I've already referred twice to my new book, Human Rights in the Constitutional Law of the United States (2013), the official publication date of which is July 31, 2013. The table of contents and introduction to the book are available here.
4. Space contraints did not permit me to develop adequately my Commonweal critique of SCOTUS's opinion in United States v. Windsor. I will present the full critique in the context of a lecture that I am due to deliver at the University of Illinois on November 6: The David C. Baum Lecture in Civil Rights and Civil Liberties. I will make the lecture available shortly after I deliver it. In the lecture, I will explain why, in my judgment, the right to equal protection--which is the American articulation of the internationally recognized human right to moral equality--is not the appropriate basis for ruling that it is unconstitutional for government to deny access to civil marriage to same-sex couples.
So, to be continued ...
July 19, 2013 in Perry, Michael | Permalink | Comments (10)
Evangelicals' Important Role re Immigration Reform
July 19, 2013 in Berg, Thomas | Permalink | Comments (1)
Michael and Rick on the DOMA Decision
Two MOJ-ers, Michael Perry and Rick Garnett, have now written for Commonweal about United States v. Windsor. Let me add my own thoughts.
Michael says, "Right decision, wrong reason." I agree with him but disagree in turn with his own reason. Michael rightly criticizes Kennedy's opinion for reducing all opposition to same-sex marriage (SSM) to "animus" against gays and lesbians or a judgment that they are inferior beings. Michael nails it when he says that Kennedy's reasoning is in turn "demeaning to all those who for a host of non-bigoted reasons uphold the traditional understanding of marriage as an essentially heterosexual institution." Michael's justification for the decision, instead, is that it upholds "the individual's [constitutional] right to moral and religious freedom." He rests this not on the special importance of marriage as a moral or religious act or relationship for gays and lesbians, but rather on the fact that rejection of SSM fails to qualify as a standard enforcing "public [rather than private] morals" (my emphasis). Michael says that "if laws are based either on a religious belief that certain conduct is immoral or on the nonreligious belief of a minority—a narrowly held belief that is widely contested—government is not truly acting to protect public morals" (emphasis in original). Since he says the opposition to SSM is not necessarily religious, his problem with it is that it's "a narrowly held belief that is widely contested."
I disagree with that both as a constitutional standard and as a conclusion on the facts here. It doesn't seem to me that we have a general constitutional right to personal freedom whenever the reason for restricting that freedom is "widely contested" and can be characterized as "a narrowly held belief." Michael's new book will no doubt marshal a powerful argument for his position, but it seems to me too close to saying "the Constitution enacts Mr. John Stuart Mill's On Liberty." As a general approach, I think we need to preserve deference to democratic decisionmaking except when there are particular interests that call for more stringent review. Moreover, on the facts, it seems to me that although opinions on marriage are changing, the opposite-sex-only view is still far from "narrowly held": it represents the substantial majority in many states, which is far different from the contraception prohibitions, which, when Murray wrote, remained in only two states, where they were usually unenforced. Michael, given your argument, do you think that Roe and Casey were rightly decided--and rightly decided simply because restrictions on abortion are "widely contested" (without some need to establish that they seriously impose on women's physical autonomy or life plans)?
Instead, I think Windsor was rightly decided but should have rested on the ground--argued in this brief and article, both co-authored by Doug Laycock and me--that some form of heightened scrutiny should apply because DOMA effectively discriminated based on sexual orientation, which should be a semi-suspect classification, and/or because it discriminated against gays and lesbians in the exercise of their fundamental right to marry. I think these grounds (1) would more honestly describe the review that the Court is applying, and (2) would avoid denigrating nearly half the population by dismissing their traditionalist views of marriage as animus and hatred, but (3) would recognize that the arguments made for excluding same-sex couples from marriage are too speculative to justify the significant unequal effect that the exclusion has on gay and lesbian couples and the children they are raising.
I share Rick's worry that the "animus" ground on which the Court actually relied not only denigrates those holding the traditionalist view, but by doing so increases the threats to religious liberty from the recognition of SSM: by suggesting that opponents "are best regarded as backward and bigoted, unworthy of respect," it "is not likely to generate compromise or accommodation and so it poses a serious challenge to [the] religious freedom" of religious social services, schools, individuals, etc. Rick, of course, doesn't agree with me that Windsor was rightly decided. And while Rick, Michael, and I have all argued for accommodations when SSM is recognized, some others would say this is misguided--that the only way to protect religious freedom is to deny SSM altogether, because (as Rick describes their argument) the campaigners for gay marriage are "aggressive and uncompromising."
Laycock and I, in our brief and article, urge that this is not necessary: it's possible to protect both same-sex marriage and religious liberty. In fact, in the long run, I think, the best hope for arguing for religious liberty is not to refuse sympathy for gay couples' efforts to live out their deep, pervasive commitments--but rather to accord them sympathy and claim similar sympathy for the deep, pervasive commitments of religious believers individually and in their institutions. It is frequently argued that activists for SSM, "aggressive and uncompromising," will never return that sympathy. But the struggle here is, as in so many other cases, to convince those in the middle. My own judgment is that as time goes on, the effort to refuse same-sex marriage will increasingly alienate those in the middle, forfeiting the chance to win them to a "live and let live" approach that will protect traditional religious organizations' ability to maintain their identities.
July 19, 2013 in Berg, Thomas | Permalink | Comments (13)
And Perry on Same-Sex Marriage and the Constitution
Michael Perry also has an interesting article over at Commonweal, "Right Decision, Wrong Reason," primarily about Justice Kennedy's opinion for the majority of the Court in Windsor and the grounds on which the majority based its legal conclusion. Michael is critical of the latter but supportive of the decision itself. Check it out as well. A bit:
In my judgment, the Court made the right decision in Windsor, but the majority was much less clear than it should have been about why DOMA’s exclusion of same-sex marriages was unconstitutional. Kennedy’s opinion for the majority should not have put any weight on the alleged “animus” of those opposed to same-sex marriage ....
Kennedy should have avoided casting such stones, for there were ample grounds for his judgment in the protection the Constitution affords to the individual’s right to religious and moral freedom.
July 19, 2013 in DeGirolami, Marc | Permalink | Comments (0)